Sunday, March 09, 2025

Fortnightly Book, March 9

 Maurice LeBlanc (1864-1941) was born to a wealthy business family, but he left behind a secure factory career in order to pursue a career in writing. He struggled for a while, but then in 1905 he received a commission to write a story that was intended to be in the gentleman-thief genre that had recently become popular due to the A. J. Raffles stories of E. W. Hornung (the brother-in-law of Sir Arthur Conan Doyle). The short story, "The Arrest of Arsène Lupin", was a smashing success, and LeBlanc began turning out several other stories about the gentleman thief, imagining him to be a French version of the very British Raffles, and to be Sherlock Holmes's equal-and-opposite in the thieving world. The latter would eventually get LeBlanc in some legal trouble from the Doyle estate; unperturbed, LeBlanc just started calling the equal-and-opposite of Lupin in the detective world, 'Herlock Sholmes'. Ironically, LeBlanc would soon have the same problems with Arsène Lupin that Doyle had with Sherlock Holmes. The character was difficult to write convincingly and it was impossible to keep up with the demand for new stories; so, like Doyle, LeBlanc would eventually try to kill off his character and yet, like Doyle, find that when a character reaches a certain level of popularity, the author no longer has complete say on whether they stay killed. Nonetheless, LeBlanc seems to have reconciled to this more easily than Doyle, buying a house and calling it "Clos Lupin". He lived his last years as World War II began to ramp up, leaving Clos Lupin out of worries of German invasion, and died of pneumonia in 1941.

I've previously done all the Sherlock Holmes stories for the Fortnightly Book, and I have wanted to do all the Lupin stories as well. I read the first one, I think, a very long time ago, and a few years ago, I listened to several of them on audiobook, and ever since they have been on the list, and I have had the entire box set sitting on my to-do pile, and I have just not gotten around to them. So let's start remedying that; the next Fortnightly Book is Arsène Lupin, Gentleman Burglar, the collection of nine short stories that started the character's career.

A Poem Draft and a Poem Re-Draft

 Carcosa

Carcosa, city sorrow-tossed,
the glory once and always lost,
in dreadful gray and dying dusk
sends up half-towers like a husk,

and here, where elsewhere gardens grow,
the trees are rotting with a glow
like ghostly phantoms dripping fear;
the grave alone can blossom here.

And all the graves there ever be
Carcossa holds like waves on sea,
including yours, which sadly states
your name and those two burning dates,

and no one walks here save the mad,
in rhythms echoing and sad,
and those who come here fade like frost,
all but these tombstones ever-lost,

for in Carcosa, far away,
and yet too near, the sunsets stay,
and time without a future sighs,
reflecting on the past that dies.


Extreme Unction 

Reminiscent,
as with some ancient memory,
but of what is above as well as what is behind,
a recollection of serenity,
too often lost,
yet always there,
descends with soothing scent,
a holy and confirming scent;
the flesh pants like a hart,
yearning for living water,
yearning to love,
with kiss on crucifix.
The heart is sick in God's presence,
sickness a distance from God,
a distance as upon a cross,
an aching distance,
a burning gap,
a purifying as if by fire.
Upon the head which knows,
upon the hands which do,
upon the body and its means,
the Spirit is given,
the oil is given,
and like the penitent thief,
stealing into paradise,
the soul shares the Passion
(its mortality the Passion),
and the spirit overflows,
redounding in splendid glory,
that the body be made
sign of its own resurrection,
the beginning of resurrection.

Saturday, March 08, 2025

Faroe-Islander Saga

 Introduction

Opening Passage:

There was a man named Grimur Kamban who was the first to settle in the Faroe Islands. In those days, a great number of men were seeking refuge from the tyranny of King Haraldur Fine-Hair; some men settled themselves in the Faroe Islands and farmed there, while other men sought land on other islands.

When Aud the Deep-Minded was traveling to Iceland, she came first to the Faroe Islands. There she married off Alofa, daughter of Thorstein the Red, from whom descends the entire family line of Faroe-Islanders called the Götuskeggjar who live on Austurey. (p. 31)

Summary: The Faereyinga saga hints at its theme in the very beginning of the work: this is the saga of the independence of the Faroe Islands, settled by men seeking to escape tyranny, who will maintain a sort of independence despite being in some ways the least significant and least powerful of the Scandinavian lands. It primarily takes place over the course of the conversion of the Faroe Islands to Christianity; as with Njal's Saga, the islands are pagan at the beginning and Christian by the end. But the role of the conversion is somewhat different; in Njal's Saga, Christianity provides the means for the resolution of the problem of Iceland spiralling out of control, whereas the primary issue in Faroe-Islander Saga is how the Faroe Islands will genuinely convert to Christianity on its own terms rather than being forced into a pseudo-conversion by the rising power of Christian Norway.

But that is the saga considered at a very abstract level. The saga is actually the story of a wily and ruthless pagan family, the family of Thrandur, one of the Götuskeggjar from the island of Eysteroy, or Austurey, as it is known today. Despite being a younger brother, Thrandur, who we are told is exceptionally lucky, manages to inherit the family farm, which he rents out as he sails away to make a fortune -- which he makes in spades, as an unlikely series of events results in his coming into a massive amount of money. Meanwhile, an accidental death leads to a feud between two other families, those of Hafgrimur of Sudoroy and the brothers Brestir and Breinir Sigmundursson of Skuvoy.  Hafgrimur gets the help of Thrandur in a course of events that leads to the death of the two brothers; Thrandur wants to kill their sons, but is prevented by his allies, so instead sells them into slavery. They end up in Norway, where, after they are freed, they are raised by an extraordinarily talented outlaw family who takes them in during a snowstorm and then teaches them to fight and track; Brestir's son, Sigmundur, marries the daughter of the family, Thurid. Sigmundur and his cousin Thorir make their way to the court of Earl Hakon, where they do very well; as a result Sigmundur receives a ring from Earl Hakon that belonged to the goddess Thorgerd and renders its bearer lucky. The boys return to the Faroe Islands, where Sigmundur has to retake his family farm by force, and the two press Thrandur for legal compensation for the death of their father. They eventually agree to travel to the court of Earl Hakon in Trondheim to have him mediate; when only Sigmundur arrives at Trondheim, Earl Hakon decides very generously for Sigmundur and Thorir, and the two then have quite the task of trying to force Thrandur to comply, because Thrandur is not the kind of person to give anything freely.

The invasion of the Jomsvikings furthers the fortunes of Sigmundur and Thorir as they join Earl Hakon to fight them off, and this leads to Sigmundur being in good favor as King Olaf Tryggvason takes the throne and Christianizes Norway. Sigmundur becomes Christian and is tasked by King Olaf with Christianizing the Faroe Islands. Thrandur becomes his major opponent in this, but his luck outmatches Thrandur's for the moment, and he effectively forces Thrandur to convert, although it is clear that the conversion is less than even skin-deep. It also massively aggravates the feud between the two families. Thrandur's foster sons (Sigurthur, Thorthur, Gautur, and Leifur) attempt to assassinate the two cousins twice, but fail both times; the escalation brings things to a head, and finally Thrandur leads a violent raid against Sigmundur's farm, thinking to catch both Sigmundur and Thorir there, but he misses them, and they are repelled by Sigmundur's household led by the very impressive Thorid. Tracked by Thrandur, Sigmundur and Thorir and a servant named Einar manage to get away, although Einar dies in the process, and reach another island. But Sigmundur's luck runs out when they are discovered by a man named Thorgrimur, who murders them both and buries the body so that no one will know that he did it.

Leifur, one of Thrandur's foster sons (and the biological son of the man whom Sigmundur had killed in order to take back his family farm), wants to marry Thora, the daughter of Sigmundur and Thorid, and Thora demands that if Leifur is even to have a chance, he must discover who killed her father and bring them to justice. Thrandur tracks it down to Thorgrimur, and by pagan death-magic is able to find the evidence that convicts Thorgrimur, who is executed for it. (Killing a man is not so great a misdeed in medieval Scandinavian society, and would under most circumstances just legally require a fine, but killing a man and then covering up the killing is a capital crime.) Leifur marries Thora, although there's some indication that Thorid, now known as Thorid Strong-Widow, only allows this because she thinks it may eventually provide a way to get back at Thrandur.

A new King of Norway, Olafur Haraldursson (more commonly known today as St. Olaf), attempts to put the Faroe Islands under the Norwegian tax regimen, but the family of Thrandur repeatedly manages to foil this. In the course of doing this, Sigurthur, Thorthur, and Gautur end up murdering the tax envoy, which estranges them from Leifur, who had befriended him. They are exiled. With there being no one cunning enough or lucky enough to oppose him, however, Thrandur is able to engineer their return, and, even more than that, is able to arrange for Leifur's and Thora's son, Sigmundur Leifursson, to be fostered by him -- despite the fact that everyone in the family knows that the young Sigmundur is effectively a hostage. Sigurthur and Gautur manage to do well for themselves and in particular marry well, but in extraordinarily suspicious ways that lead to a sharp deterioration in their reputation. Thorthur, meanwhile, decides he wants to marry Thorid Strong-Widow, which gives Thorid the beginning of the thread she needs to unravel the family of Thrandur. The sons of Thrandur are caught in a carefully laid trap and killed, although at considerable cost, and Thrandur dies of grief. The family of Leifur and Thora become the dominant family in the Faroe Islands, which become Christian because the family of Thrandur had been the last obstacle to its doing so. Nonetheless, it's because of Thrandur's resistance that the Faroe Islands becomes Christian on Faroe-Islander terms rather than by being forced into it by the much more powerful Kingdom of Norway.

Of all the sagas I have read, this was in some ways the most difficult to read because it is subtle on a level that is far beyond even the ordinary subtle irony of most sagas. From the beginning, it is clear that there is something 'off' about Thrandur. The author never tells us anything about what it is. In fact, he has a habit of going very vague at crucial points in the story. We are told that Thrandur is very lucky, but he often seems too lucky. Some of this is no doubt ties to his entanglements with pagan magic -- for instance, every time anyone tries to work directly against him, they are opposed by bad weather -- but it's more than that. If it were only one or two instances in which Thrandur somehow came out on top agains the odds, okay, that's luck. But it happens again and again, and there is too much pattern to it. Thrandur seems to be cheating at every turn. We are never told that. Everything is told at a surface level in such a way that every individual case could be interpreted as just Thrandur lucking out. But over the course of the saga, we get repetitions, each slightly different, which start to raise questions about the cases we have already read about. And the author's not telling us about how things happened, his going vague at key moments, starts to look very deliberate.

For instance, at one point an associate of Thrandur, Eldjarn, is accidentally killed; this leads to the feud between Thrandur and the sons of Brestir and Beinir. Later, however, he shows up again helping Thrandur. Perhaps the author just forgot that Eldjarn had already died, or made a mistake in confusing him with someone else? Perhaps. But then there is also the episode in which the sons of Thrandur are killed, and then their ghosts start haunting the coast, stealing things and killing people, and then they show up alive again at the most auspicious time. Are both 'deaths' in fact just deceptions perpetrated by Thrandur and his family? The text doesn't tell us -- in fact, it goes very vague at every point where it could tell us something that would tell us yay or nay. If it just happened once -- fine. If something so strange happens twice -- odd. If something so strange happens twice and the narrator keeps denying us the relevant information about what is happening -- there is something going on. There are several other examples of this, like the fact that Sigurthur and Gautur both end up marrying wealthy widows, with whom there had already been rumors that they had been having affairs, shortly after their husbands die and they avenge -- or perhaps "avenge" -- their husbands deaths. We are never told that Sigurthur and Gautur killed the husbands. In fact, we are explicitly given the death scene that leads to Gautur's good fortune, and it very definitely does not say that Gautur killed the husband. In fact, the whole scene can be read as implying someone else's doing it. But when you stop and consider the scene carefully, it doesn't actually say that, either, and everything it says is, strictly speaking, consistent with the possibility that Gautur killed the husband and then blamed someone else, killing them before they could defend themselves. When it also happens to Sigurthur, with only slight variations in the details, it becomes practically certain that the latter interpretation is right. We don't know the details -- we are denied the details -- but Thrandur's family is a frighteningly cunning lot.

That perhaps make the eventual success of Sigmundur's and Thorid's family, and the triumph of Christianity, all the more remarkable.

Favorite Passage:

Next Thrandur instructed a blazing fire be made in the fire-house, and he had four metal grates placed in a square, and Thrandur himself scored nine furrows in the earthen floor, making nine concentric circles around the square, and he sat down on a stool between the fire and the grated pen. He asked his men not to speak to him, and they stood silently by.

For a long while Thrandur sat there.

After some time had passed, a man entered the fire-house. He was all wet. Everyone recognized the man as Einar South-Islander. Einar went up to the fire and warmed his hands; he stood there a long while; then he turned and let. More time went by, and another man came into the fire-house. He went to the fire, warmed his hands, and then departed. Soon after Thorir had left, a third man came into the fire-house, a great man covered in blood, who carried his head in his hands. They all recognized him as Sigmundur Brestirsson. Sigmundure halted at a certain spot on the floor for a time, then he made his departure. (pp. 96-97)

Recommendation: Highly Recommended


***

Faroe-Islander Saga, Robert K. Painter, tr., McFarland & Company, Inc. (Jefferson, NC: 2016).

Friday, March 07, 2025

Dashed Off V

 Accidents are likenesses of substances with respect to being.

Whatever we know of a thing, we know through knowing its substance.

"Any proposition whatever concerning the order of Nature must touch more or less upon religion." C. S. Peirce

"It is impossible to define velocity without some reference to the past and to the future." Whitehead

When young, we tend to act in light of what we think might work; when old, in light of what we know will not.

Political sovereignty has the same root as human rights.

the infant as a natural icon of the promise of humanity

Freedom of speech plays an important role in making it possible to assess and diagnose the moral rot of society.

Ritual is important for medicine in providing a clear framework, putting patients at ease, simplifying the work of doctors in dealing with patients, providing people with insulation from difficult events, etc.

The formal cause of justification is divine justice as given, and it is given morally (renewal of mind), jurally (imputation of justice before the divine tribunal), and sacrally (integration into heavenly liturgy).

It is remarkable how easily socialized healthcare slides into euthanizing infants and the elderly.

"God, grant human beings the power to see in small things the common principle of things both small and great." Augustine

We only have knowledge of the future in the sense that we have knowledge of dispositions.

Interpretation of Scripture is done before God the Teacher and Judge.

The 'state of nature' was a philosophical fiction constructed to evade and overwrite the actual state from which modern states arose: that which is broadly called 'feudal'.

We find no object adequate to the depths of the potential andpromise of human loyalty and fidelity except in God.

We generally think of successions as having a first; to get an infinite succession, we start with the first and move forward. Given this, we can turn it around and think of infinite succession backward; given this, we can splice the first of the backward succession to the first of the forward succession and get infinity both ways with respect to our reference point, the dual-sided first. Then we recognize that any point could be treated as first in this way, and abstract from the first by, so to speak, spreading it everywhere.

"For by Moses the one God attuned the Holy Scriptures to the minds of many people, who would see different things in those words, all of them true." Augustine
"For God in his Christ has made in us too a heaven and earth, the spiritual and the carnal members of his Church."

The young have difficulty disentangling ethics from their insecurities, and the old have difficulty disentangling their ethics from their comforts.

Animals, plants, and landmarks get something like rights from having roles in human traditions and communities.

A continual problem in talk of representation in political philosophy is equivocation between the sense in which representative represent everyone (i.e., exercise powers on their behalf) and the sense in which they definitely don't (i.e., picking which values and principles on which to act).

"A gift is the thing given by the person who bestows what we need, such as money, food, drink, clothing, shelter, assistance, whereas the fruit is the good and upright will of the giver." Augustine

To understand the demonstrative proof, you must understand the dialectical matrix.

Augustine's Confessions move from restlessness to rest.

In creating, God makes the capacity to imitate God.

"What is the principle of movement in the soul? Clearly just as in the whole it is God, so too in this. For the divine in us somehow moves all things." Aristotle (EE 1248a)

"Christ, according to his humanity, is the altar on high of God's majesty, on which we are offered when we are incorporated into him in glory." Albert

Too much discussion of evangelism focuses on the persona of the Christian and not on the person of Christ.

agent intellect : terminative object :: possible intellect : specificative object

Both bread and wine presuppose water.

In the sacraments, words represent the Spirit.

The Holy Spirit has, indeed is, absolutely infallible Magisterium; Scripture and the Church participate in this under certain conditions as the Spirit's instruments; Ecumenical Councils and the Pope under certain conditions participate in this instrumentality as representatives of the Church.

rememorative allegory as a principle of the liturgy

the scent of distance (related to concentrations detectable to the sense of smell)
--> arguably this requires a kinaesthetic element; it is change in intensity of scent that provides distance information

Nietzsche makes amor fati to be learning how to see the necessary as beautiful.

the internal morality of trade

"Usura solum in mutuo cadit." Bernardino

It is important to grasp that much of the traditional opposition to usury was driven by bankers and merchants. (It was seen as unfair trade practice, and also as endangering the reputation of the entire profession.)

the notes of development as modes of tradition

For Sikhs, the Sri Guru Granth Sahib is in a sense doubly Guru; it embodies the spirit of the Guru verbally (Guru Arjan Dev) but also receives commission as the Guru of the Panth (Guru Gobind Singh). In this twofold aspect it carries forward the double action of a guru: to teach the truth and to form a community for the truth.

Delicacy without good sense is a dangerous combination in both aesthetics and ethics.

"A poem is a stone thrown into the pool of the mind." David West

Caesarius of Arles on the ecclesiological interpretation of Pr 31 -- Sermon 139

Suffering does not bring wisdom; reflection, even on one's suffering, sometimes does.

(1) Recognizing the normative value of our own natural good, we must recognize the normative value of natural good in other cases.
(2) The child in the womb has a natural good.

A society that respects human dignity must prepare for those who will be born into it, as well as for those who will leave it by dying.

Faith is not a preoccupation; it is title to what is not immediate, like testimony, like inheritance, like promise, a having broadly what is not had strictly, and what is more, a shared having, a one faith and not many faiths, and what is more, it is received (as indeed testimony, inheritance, and promise are).

The Bible has its authority not as read by people but as addressing them, especially in a literal manner as read aloud in synagogue or church.

the cadence of being

intelligibility as being illuminated by the intellect

The invariances of the universe are together that whereby the universe imitates the immutable divine.

A book is a social entity, and Scripture is not an exception.

"When we ask how good a man is, we do not ask what he believes or hopes, but what he loves." Augustine
"Friendship begins with one's spouse and children, and from there moves on to strangers."

We do not force concepts onto objects; they are objects because we conceive them.

"God is the cause that acts and is not acted upon." Augustine Civ. Dei 5.9

Genuine conversation presupposes the free contribution of all parties involved. If we converse, we are free.

When people try to strip metaphysics out of something, they generally make it less human.

"...love is proportionate to apprehension." Maimonides Guide 3.51
"When you walk in the way of the moral virtues, you do justice to your rational soul, giving her the due that is her right." Guide 3.53

Our first conception of the cosmos is as a confused unity.

By prayer, even considered only as a human activity, we given things a relational status.

NB that Maimonides holds that prayer is a duty in the Law, whereas Nahmanides holds that it is not but rather a natural & spontaneous response to God's lovingkindness.
-- Maimonides' foundation for his position: Ex 23:25, Dt 13:5, Dt 11:13, Dt 6:13, Nm 10:9

"Know that all the practices of wroship, such as the reading of Torah, prayer, and the performance of the other commandments, have only teh end of training you to occupy yourself with His commandments, may He be exalted, rather than with matters pertaining to this world; you should act as if you were occupied with Him, may He be exalted, and not with that which is other than He." Maimonides Guide 3.51
"We, the community of those who adhere to Law, say that He knows with one single knowledge teh many and numerous things. For as far as He, may He be exalted, is concerned, insigths do not differ because of the difference of the things known, as is the case with respect to us." Guide 3.20

R. Joshua b. Levi: Hallelujah is the most perfect kind of praise, because it includes both praise and the Name (BT Perakhim 117A).

Paraphrases of literal expressions are often only indirect or approximate, so we should expect the same of paraphrases of figurative expressions.

broadcastmindedness (Knox): "the habit of taking over, from self-constituted mentors, a ready-made, standardized philosophy of life, instead of constructing, with however imperfect materials, a philosophy of life for oneself"

Professional ethics is inherently casuistical.

History absolves no one.

Every 'bounded ideality' has within it an abstract form or general structure, a historical representation, a functional timeline, geography, demographic, etiology, etc., that conforms to its general principles.

Interpreting the Good Samaritan as a figure of Christ, "Go and do likewise" is a command to be Christlike. Cf. Knox: "The mercy of God shown to us in the Incarnation is to be the model for all our acts of human mercy."

The Church is as if God, finding the treasure of Christ buried in the field of humanity, bought the whole field for the sake of the treasure.

The work of the vineyard is not to make the plants grow but to provide what they need.

Civil rights are always deteriorating and so always needing to be renewed.

The rosary is a conceptual prayer-garden.

"If you start by treating the uniformity of nature as a hypothesis and no more, you will find your hypothesis is upset by every recorded case of witches flying, tables turning, Saints being levitated, oracles coming true, horoscopes being verified, broken limbs being cured by faith-healing, and the like." Knox
"Everybody knows that all hypotheses are in the last resort partial and insecure as a representation of truth; at the best, they cannot be postiively proved, they can only escape refutation."
"The witness of power needs to be supplemented: that does not mean that it can be dispensed with."

It is easy to prepare oneself intellectually for matters of faith; the difficulty is preparing oneself morally.

All sacraments, major and minor, are transsignified and transfinalized.

Someone's being blameworthy implies that it is permissible to blame them.

Moving from confused and obscure cognition to distinct and clear cognition is generally a slow process requiring custom-tailored adjustment.

Our knowledge of our concepts is reflective, not direct, and is expanded by causal reasoning from communicating, whether by word or deed, as well as classificatory extrapolation from perception and practice. In a prephilosophical posture, things are known conceptually but the concepts are 'in use' rather than 'under study'. Puzzles about things lead to reflection on the concepts that we use; this is often done briefly, loosely, and in a limited way. The Socratic innovation is to take this reflection to a full study.

In practical classification, classes often do not correspond to unified concepts.

Our first articulated believing presupposes the guidance of authority.

"No explanation of the universe can be regarded as adequate which does not take account of all the phenomena of the universe, and among these human intelligence is surely not the least important." E. W. Trueman Dicken
"Morality is no less of an art than is the making of violins."

The point of the Sermon on the Mount is not the replacement of the Law but the transfiguration of the Law.

categories -> transcendentals -> immaterial being

Gratitude to God expands the circle of human beings to whom and for whom we must be thankful.

the motivational state of rule-regulation (Darwall) -- the commitment to abiding by rules of conventions of justice

self-love, private benevolence, public benevolence
(these can be regarded as three categories of wanting to do good, classified according to whose good)

Classification by smell is arguably the classification that best fits nominalist and empiricist accounts of classification.

Thursday, March 06, 2025

Links of Note

 * Ernesto Priani, Ramon Llull, at the SEP

* Kevin J. Harrelson, Richard T. Greener and the Abolitionist Moment in American Philosophy, at "Blog of the APA"

* Carlos Cortissoz, Souls Within a Soul: The City-Soul Analogy Revisited (PDF)

* Edmund Stewart, The First Universities? Ancient Greek Philosophical Schools, at "Antigone"

* Doug Campbell, Why did the ancient Greeks avoid human dissection?, at "Plato's Fish-Trap: Ancient Natural Philosophy"

* Colin Chamberlain, How to Eat a Peach: Malebranche on the Function of the Passions (PDF)

* Brendan Hodge, Is Easter actually 'late' this year?, at "The Pillar"

* Francesca Mezzenza & Gabriel Scheidecker, Hegemony and Childcare, at "Aeon"

* Marshall Bierson, Understanding Anscombe's Absolutism (PDF)

* Andreas Wimmer, Seungwon Lee, and Jack LaViolette, The Spread of Romantic Nationalism across Europe: A Case of Ideational Diffusion, at "Broadstreet"

* Theresa Tallien, What Was Courtship?

* T. Parker Haratine, Augustine on memory, the mind, and human flourishing (PDF)

* Ryan Burge, The Truth Isn't Out There: Religion and Belief in Aliens, at "Graphs About Religion"

Wednesday, March 05, 2025

Hyper Christou Presbeuomen

Therefore from now on, we recall no one according to the flesh. Though too we knew Christ according to the flesh, yet now we no longer know. Therefore, if anyone in Christ -- a new creature. The original has perished; see, the new comes to be. And all from God, the one having restored us to himself through Christ, and having given us the service of restoration, how God was in Christ, the world restoring to Himself, not counting their lapses against them, and having placed in us the reason of restoration.

Therefore for Christ we negotiate, as though God is summoning through us. We beg on behalf of Christ: Be restored to God! The one unknowing of sin, he made sin for us, so that we might become God's justice in him. And also, cooperating, we urge you not to receive God's grace in an empty way.

For he says: At the approved time, I heard you, and in the day of safety, I rescued you. See, now is the well-approved time; see, now is the day of safety.

[2 Corinthians 5:16-6:2, my very rough translation. Like much of 2 Corinthians, this is a bit of a tangle. The word I've translated here as 'restoration' is often translated as 'reconciliation'; it can also mean 'change' and seems sometimes to be used to mean something like 'atonement'. The word I've translated as 'negotiate' literally means 'be elders' (it is related to the word presbyter, usually translated as 'elder', which gives us the word 'priest'), but age is not the key thing; to be an elder is to have a position of responsibility and honor. Thus the verb is often translated as 'be ambassadors'; we could also translate it as 'represent'.]

No Maps of His Soul Have I Penned

 Loyalty
by Berton Braley 

He may be six kinds of a liar,
He may be ten kinds of a fool,
He may be a wicked highflyer
Beyond any reason or rule;
There may be a shadow above him
Of ruin and woes to impend,
And I may not respect, but I love him,
Because -- well, because he's my friend. 

 I know he has faults by the billion,
But his faults are a portion of him;
I know that his record's vermilion,
And he's far from the sweet Seraphim;
But he's always been square with yours truly,
Ready to give or to lend,
And if he is wild and unruly,
I like him -- because he's my friend. 

 I criticize him but I do it
In just a frank, comradely key,
And back-biting gossips will rue it
If ever they knock him to me!
I never make diagrams of him,
No maps of his soul have I penned;
I don't analyze -- just love him,
Because -- well, because he's my friend.

Berton Braley was a popular American poet in the first half of the twentieth century; he was newspaper-syndicated and was the sort of poet whose poems, often humorous or motivational, newspaper readers would clip out and share, or have their children memorize.

Tuesday, March 04, 2025

Beattie on Vestment

 I find that James Beattie has a brief discussion of the Aristotelian category of echein/habitus, in his work, Theory of Language, Part II, Chapter II. In context, he's looking at adverbs, and he considers a possible way that had been proposed of categorizing adverbs in terms of Aristotle's categories. He goes through the categories briefly, assigning adverbs, and notes that there's no obvious English adverbs for the category of habitus, although he recognizes that this doesn't mean you couldn't have any, and he even gives a hypothetical example of how a particular etymology, if it had gone a different way than it actually did, might have delivered one. (Our contemporary English perhaps gives an actual example, in nattily.) Then he has a slight digression discussing the category itself:

By the by, I cannot see, for what purpose Aristotle made a separate category of the tenth; for to me it seems included in some of the preceding. A crown is as really a substance, as the head that wears it, and may last a thousand years longer . Or, if it is the having of the crown, or the being crowned, that distinguishes the category, as when we say, a crowned head, then crowned denotes a quality perceived by sense, and so belongs to the third predicament. Indeed this is not the only objection that might be made to the doctrine of the categories. Whoever treats of it in the way of detail, and without prejudice, will find, if I mistake not, that in some things it is redundant, and in others defective. 

This is unsurprising -- Beattie, like many early modern philosophers, has a dislike for 'the schoolmen'. The substance argument is very much the one later given Bentham, although Beattie has perhaps more justification for it -- when he defined the category originally, he said that it "denotes something additional and exterior to a substance, but not a part of it" (pp. 159-160), whereas Bentham is purportedly deriving his discussion from Sanderson but ignores Sanderson's explicit definition of the category in terms of adjacency. 

But Beattie is also in many ways a more educated man than Bentham, and unlike (apparently) Bentham was directly familiar with Aristotle himself, and so he considers a more adequate way of thinking of it, in terms of "the having" (the literal meaning of echein) of the other substance. His suggestion that in that case it should be reduced to quality (the third predicament, counting substance and quantity as the first two) is interesting. There is of course a form of quality that shares a cognate name with the tenth category -- hexis, or acquired disposition (translated into Latin with the same word for this category, habitus), is derived from one of the forms of echein -- so this is not implausible. (And makes clear that, despite the fact he's not making a show of it, Beattie's argument is informed by his familiarity with the actual Greek.)  There is in fact a very good modern article -- Abraham Edel's 1975 "Aristotle's Categories and the Nature of Categorial Theory" (I highly recommend it) -- that proposes something of the kind, leaning very heavily on the etymology. 

Nonetheless, I think this is fairly certainly a mistake. Being crowned is not really all that much like being skilled or virtuous (the most obvious forms of habitus in the quality sense), and Beattie's particular assumption that being crowned is a 'sensible quality' is probably related to the fact that as a Scottish common sense theorist he has a very broad interpretation of what counts as a 'sensible quality'. Obviously being crowned is not immediately sensible in the way that being red is; you have to have an intellectual understanding of what a crown is to see that someone is crowned.

What is true is that we sometimes treat being skilled, or virtuous, or red, or any kind of quality possession, on the model of being clothed. This is, again, a metaphorical use, and presumably happens because vestment is more sensible and imaginable than quality possession. (And there are sometimes direct connections. We can wear utility belts and other useful things, for instance, and these are things that can be instrumental to skill, and thus, in actual use, expressions of skill.) We can use vestment as a model for any kind of having, and we especially use it as a metaphor for contingent having (i.e., where what is had is something acquired, or something that depends on particular circumstances); even though the senses of 'having' are themselves very far from being univocal.

Monday, March 03, 2025

The Sheeted Mists Like Baffled Hosts Retire

 Sunrise
by George Heath 

Slow creeps the light athwart the concave still,
Steals a low whisper on the breathless calm,
Bringing the scent of opening flowers, a balm;
Breaks o'er the earth a grand, a rapturous thrill,
The chant of waters, and the song-bird's trill;
The clouds fold up their curtains, snowy white;
The sleeping stars fade noiselessly from sight.
Bright Phoebus mounts above the crimson hill;
The sheeted mists like baffled hosts retire,
Wan Zephyr comes to wanton with the flowers,
The stream meanders on, a string of fire,
And light and music fill earth's sylvan bowers!
Bright dewdrops shine and tremble everywhere:
O Sceptic, look and blush, for God is there!

Crown of Thanksgiving

 O Lord, behold your Church, saved by your Cross, and your flock bought with your precious Blood, offers a crown of thanksgiving in faith to you, O High Priest of justice who has exalted her by your abasement. And, like a glorious Bride, she rejoices and exults in you, O glorious Bridegroom. In the strength of the Truth, raise the walls of her salvation, and establish priests within her, to be ambassadors of peace on behalf of her children.

[From the Basilica Hymn for The Week Beginning the Great Fast (Sawma/Lent), in The Book of Before and After: The Liturgy of the Hours of the Church of the East, Fr. Andrew Younan, ed. and tr., The Catholic University of America Press (Washington, DC: 2024), p. 475. The Book of Before and After is the the liturgy of the hours (Divine Office) for the churches of the Church of East, i.e., the Church that grew up east of the Roman Empire (the Church that grew up inside the Roman Empire being the 'Church of the West'). Churches in the Church of the East tradition are the Assyrian Church of the East (sometimes just called the Church of the East, which includes the Chaldean Syrian Church of India), the Ancient Church of the East (a relatively recent split-off from the former), the Chaldean Catholic Church (which is in communion with Rome), and the Syro-Malabar Catholic Church (also in communion with Rome). This particular version of The Book of Before and After is specifically designed for the use of Chaldean Catholics. 

In the churches of the Church of the East -- as almost everywhere except the Latin Church -- Lent begins today; Ash Wednesday is a Latin Church tradition, and is not celebrated in the East at all, except in Maronite and (sometimes) Syro-Malabar parishes that serve a lot of Latin Catholics. The fasting custom for Chaldean Catholics is generally that the first, middle and last days of Lent are days of fast and abstinence, where abstinence covers not only meat but also dairy and eggs, and Fridays in Lent are days of abstinence from meat; there is no fasting on Sunday. Fasting consists of eating nothing between midnight and noon and only moderately the rest of the day.]

Sunday, March 02, 2025

John of St. Thomas on Vestment

 Continuing on with the previous posts on the Aristotelian category of habitus/echein, I was curious about what John of St. Thomas (a.k.a., John Poinsot) -- also from the seventeenth century, although unlike Sanderson in the thick of the final scholastic flowering of the Baroque period -- says on the subject. John's interpretation of the category is heavily influenced by the Summa totius logicae Aristotelis (Opusculum 48); it is regarded as spurious today, and was often thought to be such in the seventeenth century, with, however, John of St. Thomas as one of its major defenders. From his Cursus Philosophicus:

About the category of habitus. Its definition is: "what is the adjacency of bodies and those things which are about the body." For just as a thing is rendered located by its adjacent and surrounding place, and by its subjection to time, so from the vestment around it, it is said to be clothed. Hence that is false that some say: habitus is a certain mode which is in the human body, by which it is rendered apt to be vested, which does not apply to other bodies. However, this does not render a man vested, but capable of being vested rather than merely nude. But it is clear that the category of habitus takes away nudity, since it renders him vested: therefore it does not consist in that mode, which is compatible with actual nudity. On account of which habitus is drawn out of the adjacency of clothing, just as where is from place. Nor does it prevent vestment from being a substance in itself. For since its application is accidental, it makes an accidental denomination and an accidental category, just as a vessel is said to be golden or wooden denominatively; but it is not a pure extrinsic denomination, but is drawn from an adjacency in man, as where is drawn from place.

 And so it is said by St. Thomas “habitus is a medium between clothing and having-clothing”, v Met., lect. xx, and 1-11, qest. XLIX, art. 1. Whence it comes that animals, even if they are covered with hair or are armed with claws, are not from them denominated as vested, because they are parts of the body. But if they are surrounded by some clothing, as a horse harnessed or armed, they are denominated by this category, as man by vestment. 

 The properties of these [last six] categories can easily be seen in St. Thomas’s Opusc. XLVIII, treating of each. Almost all of them are not susceptible of more and less, and do not have a contrary, save for action and passion, which have both. Habitus is also said to be susceptible of more and less not according to intensity or remission, but according to many or fewer clothings, as St. Thomas says, cited Opuscul., treatise on habit, chap. 3. However, it does not have a contrary, because it does not have intension and remission.

(My rough translation. John of St. Thomas uses two different words for clothed here, indutum and vestitum; they are used as synonyms, but I have used 'clothed' for indutum and its cognates and 'vested' for vestitum and its cognates, just to mark them in the translation.) While very briefly stated, I take it that John is here arguing for the idea that habitus is a real mode or aspect of a human being in such a way that becoming clothed changes the one who is clothed (they are no longer nude), which is due to the adjacency/adjoining.

And a little later, talking about the 'coordination' of the category (the coordination of a category, which is, I think, a term that comes from Suarez, is the system of genera under it), Poinsot says:

Habitus, which is a supreme genus, is divided by St. Thomas, Opusc. XLVIII, into arms and vestments, Arms, into offensive and defensive, each of which has various species. Vestments, into the vestment of men and of beasts, as horses are adorned with saddle, bridle, arms, etc. Vestments, into various modes of clothing according to diverse adjacencies, such as a tunic, shoe, hat, etc., which species are not taken from the material or art by which the vestments are made, but from the diverse way in which they are vested and covered. Also reduced to this category are wall ornaments, which are not properly vestments.

John of St. Thomas diverges slightly from St. Thomas's actual view as found in the Commentary on the Physics III, lect. 5, n. 14 (322); while St. Thomas does think that vestments for beasts are reduced to this category, he seems to be implying that it is not in a strict and proper sense but insofar as they 'are brought to human use' (in hominis usum veniunt). That is, in a much later vocabulary, the vestments of beasts are vestments not 'naturally' but 'morally', i.e., by human will (in something like the way, perhaps, that corporations are legal persons and so considered on the model of substances). The category is explicitly stated to be a special category for human beings. Op. 48, which is John's major influence here, says something similar, but perhaps more ambiguously:

Hence this category is only appropriate to humans. But it is true that we also vest and arm certain animals with external vestments and arms, for we vest apes and harness horses; and in this mode the category is able to pertain to them.

One way this could be read, however, is as saying that vestment applied to apes and horses is due to human beings but is nonetheless vestment in the proper sense. Given how Poinsot describes the coordination of the category, he has to be taking it to mean this when he cites it: vestments of beasts are a species of vestment and not, as seems to be the case with Aquinas in the Physics, an extended sense arising from how we use animals.

Mark K. Spencer has a very nice article on this, The Category of Habitus: Artifacts, Accidents, and Human Nature, which situates John's view in the context of the different scholastic views on how to understand the category. (I am personally inclined to think, however, that Spencer's own account of habitus, drawing from Poinsot and Joseph Owens, is both too narrow and too wide, although interestingly for the same reason: it ties the category too tightly to human use, and therefore also includes too many things that fall under human use. It's the old proper/extended problem, a serious problem in working out this category, because, again, we use this category as a model for all sorts of other things, thus leading to a huge number of metaphorical uses. Because of this, it's difficult to draw the line appropriately between proper and extended uses.)

Saturday, March 01, 2025

Sanderson on Vestment

 I thought, given my last post, that I would translate Robert Sanderson's account of the category of Habitus from the Logicae Artis Compendium, so that it is more clear what Bentham would have had in front of him (not that he seems to have used it beyond the mnemonic verse, which is the only thing he references on this particular point); it's also interesting in giving us the 'Cliff's Notes' version of how it was understood in the seventeenth century. Seventeenth century textbooks like this are almost always extremely simplified versions of more sophisticated discussions in centuries prior. The universities were in bad shape by this point, and students, rather than doing any deep study or original work, mostly just crammed off compendia and summaries and vocabulary lists, which is one reason for the bad reputation of 'the schoolmen' in the early modern period. Nonetheless, sometimes the textbooks show that genuinely interesting things survived the slow but massive (and remarkably deliberate) brain-damaging of the entire scholastic super-edifice, which by the seventeenth century had been dumbed-down to almost nothing except in a few last redoubts like Coimbra and Louvain. Sanderson was a tutor at Oxford, which was not at all a shining example of university excellence in the seventeenth century, although he himself was fairly impressive (besides this textbook, which became one of the standard logic texts, he became an Anglican bishop famous for his preaching as well as a quite competent Regius Professor of Divinity). 

In any case, Sanderson on Habitus:

Habitus is the adjacency of the body and of those things which surround the body: by which the one having, these are said to be had. 'The body having' is the substance; 'The thing had' is an artificial form of the fourth species of quality: the application of this to that is this category of Habitus. Its property is to always be in many; in the having, namely, and in the had: but for different reasons. For it is in the having body, as in a subject; it is in the had thing, as in a cause. 

Everything pertaining to this: 

 1. Kinds of vestments: whether they are worn for the sake of Necessity, as being Shod, Tunicate; or for distinction, as being Ringed, Trousered; or simply for being Adorned, as being Armored, Saddled, Tasselled, etc. 

2. Possession, as being Wealthy, being Beneficed, being Described, being Named, etc., and those things that are similar to these.

(My rough translation.) 'Adjacency' could also be translated as 'adjoining'. The fourth species of quality is 'form and figure'. It's interesting that Sanderson assumes that the form must be artificial; covering oneself with leaves would perhaps not count, although maybe 'artificial form' is being used broadly here. Nonetheless, it's interesting that Sanderson holds that in being clothed that we are related to a qualitative trait of the clothes. I suppose that makes some sort of sense -- nobody wears a shirt unless it can be draped over their frame in a way that to some extent fits the frame, because the appropriate draping is what the shirt itself is and does in being worn as a shirt. Besides the explicitly mentioned quality, several other categories are clearly implied as presupposed here: substance and quantity (body), relation (adjacency), where (those things surrounding the body), action and passion (in the had as in a cause).

The examples gave me some trouble; what Latin I have simply doesn't extend very far into words for early modern words for clothes and the like. And, frankly, I don't understand Sanderson's division at all. Why are Shod and Tunicate classed under 'for the sake of necessity' but Trousered under 'for the sake of distinction', and Armored under 'merely for adornment'? I have no idea what principle of classification is going on here. But perhaps this is not intended to be a real classification; the relevant class is just 'kinds of vestments', all together, and Sanderson is simply telling us that all the reasons why one might wear something are relevant. (Notice, incidentally, that he puts 'Saddled' here, thus implicitly providing his answer to whether a horse being saddled counts in this category.)

The second class of Habitus, however, is even more perplexing, and I suspect that Sanderson is just going along with the name of the category ('what is had') rather than having any particular reason for thinking that your having a name is an 'adjacency of a body and what is around that body'. All of this class, I think, would really be metaphorical cases of vestment (in the case of Benefices, literally metaphorical, if you will pardon the expression, because the language of vestment and investiture is actually used as a metaphor to describe it). For purely logical reasons, that perhaps does not matter so much, since the logic would work much the same whether we are being literal or metaphorical, but 'possession' would make this category a massive hodge-podge of very different things whose relations to the actual description of the category are loose at best. Nonetheless, the metaphorical cases are quite important; we use the category as a sort of model or template for talking about a lot of other, very different, topics, namely, whenever one thing can be said to belong to a different thing.

Friday, February 28, 2025

The Category of Vestment

In his  Essay on Logic, Jeremy Bentham tackles (as one might expect from the title) the subject of logic, all done with his characteristic unearned confidence and obnoxious curmudgeonliness. No one could learn very much about logic from the essay, I think, but there are occasionally interesting things. When talking about the Aristotelian categories (of which he seems to have only secondhand and limited knowledge), he spends an extended amount of time on the tenth category, habitus (echein), which gets various translations as Possession, Having, Vestment, Clothing, and so forth, the category for things like 'shod', 'clothed', 'dressed', and so forth. Bentham's sarcastic comments on the subject are actually a good way to think through the category.

Habitus, vesture, human clothing, for such is the intimation given by the corresponding portion of the illustrative distich, nec tunicatus ero.  

The illustrative distich is from Robert Sanderson's mnemonic verse in his Logicae Artis Compendium, which is Bentham's primary source on the history of logic. The distich is:

Arbor Sex Servos Fervore Refrigerat Ustos,
Ruri Cras Stabo, nec Tunicatus ero.

In English, that would mean roughly, "The tree cools six servants burned from the heat; I will stand in the field tomorrow, but not clothed."  But, of course, it's a mnemonic; each capitalized word in the original gives an example of the category.  

But clothing, human clothing, is it not a substance? Here, then, we have given, in the character of the name of a predicament distinct from all the rest, an article included under one of them, viz. the first.

More insightful than it looks; that which is worn is indeed a substance, and this is the distinctive feature of habitus as a category. Some people suggest that Aristotle's original intention for the category was that it be a rest state reached by change, which seems more general than Aristotle had in view, although it would make some sense. The traditional list of ten categories was long known to divide: the first four categories (substance, quality, quantity, relation) and the last six categories (action, passion, when, where, posture, having). The latter, which came to be known as the sex principia, all seem clearly to presuppose the category of relation in some way (Bentham, jumping on this, previously claimed that they all just reduce to relation), and one way to understand the division is take the first four to be categories specifically concerned with being (complete actuality) and the final six to be specifically concerned with changing (incomplete actuality). However, in part because of the influence of Aristotle's examples, it was also natural to take being clothed as a central feature of this particular category. But this works as well, and ironically, it is precisely for what Bentham is criticizing. Clothing is when one substance becomes accident-like relative to another substance, without being incorporated as a substantial part. In wearing shoes, you take a different substance, the shoes, and you use them in such a way that you yourself change from being unshod to being shod; the shoes become as-if accidents to you. 

The accident strictly speaking is the state of wearing; but in the state of wearing another substance becomes predicable indirectly of you, as an adjunct of you. This is the distinctive feature of the category, and contrasts with the other five of the sex principia, all of which seem to be presupposed by this category. The Thomistic way of accounting for the sex principia is that they involve attribution to a subject of something beyond itself (which is why they presuppose relation). Action and passion are the categories for which the 'something beyond' is a cause or an effect; when, where, and posture are the categories for which the 'something beyond' is a measure (in particular, a change or a container, with the latter occurring in two different ways); and vestment is when the 'something beyond' is adjoined.

Late scholastics sometimes divided this category into ornament and equipment; it's clear that these are not mutually exclusive (shoes are both for use and for adornment), but these do seem to be the primary candidates for how one substance can become an adjunct for you. One substance can be adjoined to another as a sort of closely connected sign (adorned) or as a sort of closely connected tool (equipped).

 Clothing, a predicament distinct from substance? On equal ground might additional predicaments, in any number, be stated as having existence, as being entitled to a place upon the list, many of them, perhaps most, a better title. 

Bentham very notably provides no examples at all of anything that might be at least equally entitled to a place on the list. It is very difficult to come up with another category that definitely should be on the list, in part because (whether you think the original discussions in Aristotle had any principled scheme behind them or not) the list does seem to cover most of the things we predicate of things. And on the other side, it's hard to deny that we do, in fact, treat clothing in a special way as if it were almost part of what it clothes, and that this does affect what we say of things that are clothed. Even if you held, like Bentham, that the category is in some sense arbitrary and non-natural, that doesn't change the fact that we do in fact treat clothing in a different way from the way we treat everything else, and our language does in fact reflect this. There are things other than clothing in the strict sense that we do give special treatment -- you can say of someone that he is housed, for instance, in the sense of possessing a house, but one could argue that this falls under this category as an unusual case of non-clothing having something broadly like the relation to us that normally only clothing has. Clothing is a very good candidate for being the paradigmatic case, even if one held that, strictly speaking, the category also has to include things that are not strictly what we would call clothing. (One could also argue that any non-clothing cases are cases in which the category is predicated metaphorically, by a figure of speech, rather than properly.)

A curious predicament, a predicament, the exemplification of which is mere matter of contingency, a predicament which, at one time, had no existence, which in one place has, in another place has not, existence at this present time. 

 Before eating of the fatal apple, neither Adam, nor Eve his wife, had any clothing,—had possession, or so much as any idea of any such predicament. In fact, it had not any exemplification or any existence. At the very instant of its being placed, the first fig leaf that was ever placed, gave birth to this predicament, gave birth to the first individual from which the species, such as it is, pregnant with all the individuals that ever belonged to it, took its rise.

Some of the scholastics, like Thomas Aquinas, held that it is in fact true that this category is only properly predicated of human beings, so there would be no proper exemplification of it prior to the existence of human beings. Bentham has a tendency to dismiss things without giving any reason why, and this is a good case. He doesn't give us any actual reason to think it is absurd that human beings using human language might have a class of predications that completely presupposes something done by human beings. This is particularly the case, since Bentham thinks all accidents are "fictitious entities"; only substances are "real entities", so most of the categories don't have a real exemplification at all, being at best ways we linguistically compare and contrast substances. Fictitious entities, as Bentham understands the term, don't actually exist; they arise from the limitations of language. So it's hard to see why he's being so sarcastic about it. And likewise, it's not an absurdity that the first instance where we could predicate of something that it was clothed, required the invention of clothing.

There is something striking about the idea of human beings inventing an entirely new category. Nonetheless there are a few puzzles with Aquinas's position, which occasionally come up in scholastic discussions. Walls can be tapestried, which seems quite a bit like clothing, and in fact, statues can be dressed in clothes. Even more plausibly, horses can be shod and saddled, dogs and cats can be collared, and the like. On Aquinas's view, these are all extended senses based on the fact that by human intervention we can give an artificial relation to them on the model of our own clothing. Dogs themselves don't really wear collars; we put leather or cloth strips around dog's neck on the model of necklaces and collars in human beings, and then by a figure of speech treat the dog as wearing a collar.

I confess I'm not entirely convinced by this, in the sense that I can fully see that there would be a difference between the human cases and the cases of tapestried walls, saddled horses, and collared dogs, but I don't really see why that would affect either the predication or relation. Yes, these cases are derivative cases causally, but if you put sweater on a dog, it seems to be more than merely figuratively wearing a sweater. There are even purely natural cases, like the hermit crab with his adventitious shell, that seem difficult to distinguish from our wearing of clothes. To be sure, we often use this category metaphorically; we might say that the armadillo is armored, which is a figure of speech because what we are calling 'armor' is quite clearly just a part of the armadillo. But if we went around saying that the hermit crab was shelled, it's not at all clear why we would think that we were saying that the hermit crab was wearing the shell figuratively. If vestment is the category in which one substance is predicated of another substance specifically as adjoined to it, then the hermit crab's being shelled seems to count as vestment, despite no human intervention. And if that's the case, then it seems we should treat the cases of the horse's being saddled and the dog's being collared as vestment as well.

Perhaps St. Thomas is thinking of the category as being linked particularly to action. We, ourselves, wear clothes; being shod, despite the passive construction, is something we do as well as something done to us. Being shod is not something horses do; it is only something done to horses.  This distinction between active vestment and passive vestment does seem important for many purposes. But passion is a category just like action, so I'm not sure that this would make a difference. We can distinguish cases in which we clothe ourselves and in which we are clothed by another. If someone puts clothes on you while you are asleep, for instance, you still seem to be clothed in the proper sense.

Thursday, February 27, 2025

The Origins of the Maronite Catholic Church (Re-Post)

This is a lightly revised re-post from 2023.

 

This week is interesting in the Maronite calendar of saints, because it includes a number of specifically Maronite saints: 

 February 27: St. Thalaleus, Disciple of St. Maron 

 February 28: Ss. Koura and Marana, Disciples of St. Maron 

 March 1: St. Domnina, Disciple of St. Maron & St. Eudokia of Baalbek 

 March 2: St. John Maron 

 So I thought I would say something about the origins of the Antiochene Syriac Maronite Church, a sui juris Eastern Catholic church in communion with Rome. 'Origins' because in a sense it has more than one. 

 Christianity, of course, has extensive roots in Syria and Lebanon; Antioch was where the Christians were first called 'Christian' and the bishops of Antioch in all of the apostolic churches have traditionally traced their see to St. Peter himself. The area is filled with the memory of ancient saints and martyrs. For instance, the Eudokia of Baalbek who is commemorated by the Maronites on March 1, and who is also known as Eudokia of Heliopolis, was a wealthy young woman who converted, gave away all of her wealth to the poor, and joined a convent; according to tradition, she was beheaded around 107. Many more could be added to the list. But one who particularly interests us is St. Maron, whose feast day is February 9. 

 St. Maron, or Maroun, or Maro, was born in Syria in the 4th century. According to some stories he had been a fellow student with St. John Chrysostom at one point, but what we definitely know is that he became an open-air hermit in Cyrrhus, near Antioch. Open-air eremitism is a particularly rigorous form of ascetic life; it means exactly what it sounds like it means: he lived in the open air, with only a small tent that he used only for the worst weather conditions, on a hill where a pagan temple had once stood. Syria is a region that has fairly significant temperature extremes over the year -- it gets fairly cold in the winter and very hot in the summer. It also occasionally has severe sandstorms in spring and autumn. It's not really camping country. People would occasionally visit hermits in those days to ask for prayers and the like, and over time, St. Maron developed a reputation as an effective healer, and people began to come in droves. According to Theodoret of Cyr, who wrote a book about ascetics living in the area around Antioch at this time, his reputation was not merely for physical healing, but for spiritual healing -- he could heal physical illness, but also things like anger and greed. A result was that people also began imitating him, and trying the open-air ascetic life themselves. The most important of these was a man we call St. James the Solitary, whose feast day is November 26, who also gained a widespread reputation. 

A spontaneous ascetic movement grew up around St. Maron and St. James, and this is the first origin of the Maronites, as a religious movement. St. Maron eventually came down with an illness and died, but the movement he unintentionally started continued to flourish. Many saints arose in the context of this movement. St. Abraham the Hermit, whose feast is February 14, took the Maronite life to Lebanon, where he preached in the area around Mount Lebanon and was later made bishop of Harran. St. Limnaeus was a student of another hermit (possibly also inspired by St. Maron), St. Thalassius, and afterward became a student of St. Maron himself; St. Thalassius and St. Limnaeus share a feast day on February 22. St. Thelalaeus the Weeper, whose feast is February 27, lived in a cage made out of a barrel. He had the gift of tears, so he wept for his sins very often. He happened to set up his barrel not far from a pagan temple, and so ended up preaching to pagans who came by, curious about the man living in a barrel, and converted many of them. St. Marana and St. Koura (or Cyra), whose feast is February 28, lived at Beroea in a crevice in the rocks with no roof, and St. Koura also kept a vow of silence. They did not leave the crevice at all; they built a house nearby where lived volunteers who passed them food through a narrow opening. St. Domnina the Younger, whose feast day is March 1, was a woman from a very wealthy family in Antioch; she started living in a hut in her mother's garden, veiling her face, and eating nothing but lentils. Like St. Thelalaeus, she also had the gift of tears. An entire religious community of women grew up around her, maintaining themselves by doing basic manual labor and carding wool. Many more could be added, and the kinds of asceticism they practiced were of all kinds. Monasteries and convents as well as hermitages began sprouting up.

So things went for a while, and the Maronite movement did not slow down, and it played a major role in the spiritual life of the patriarchate of Antioch. But crisis would hit in the early seventh century, when a civil war broke out, including a revolt in Antioch. The exact details are murky; the entire social situation seems to have deteriorated; but it is likely that Patriarch St. Anastasius II of Antioch (whose feast day is December 21) was assassinated by Monophysites in the course of a riot. The situation continued to be bad, so the Emperor and Patriarch of Constantinople got together and decided to appoint a titular patriarch of Antioch, who would reside in Constantinople. Exactly how this plan came into effect, we don't know; the entire period is a period of tumult, and so it may have been intended as a temporary measure until things quieted down, but in any case it ended up not being temporary, and lasted about a century. Needless to say, this was not popular among the monasteries around Antioch. What's more, things grew worse, as Muslim armies invaded Syria in a major campaign in the 630s. The monks seem to have seen that they were cut off and would likely not have a resident patriarch in any near future at this rate, so led by the major monastery in the area, the Monastery of St. Maroun on the Orontes, a major stronghold of Chalcedonian Christianity in the area, the bishops of Syria elected their own patriarch in 685 without any regard for either the Emperor or the Patriarch of Constantinople. We know remarkably little about this patriarch, St. John Maron, before his ascension, but he is said to have studied for a time in Constantinople and to have been the Monastery of St. Maroun's best teacher. Obviously they needed some recognition for the move, and Constantinople would obviously not have given it; so they went to Rome, where St. Sergius I was Pope. And while St. Sergius seems himself to have been born in Sicily, his family was Syrian from the area around Antioch. According to Maronite tradition, St. Sergius recognized St. John Maron as Patriarch of Antioch and All the East. Constantinople's line of titular patriarchs continued, and in the eighth century came back to Antioch; the Greek Orthodox and the Melkite Catholic patriarchal lineages for Antioch both descend from that return.

With St. John Maron, the Maronite movement, while continuing to be a movement, also became a Church, and this fusion of ascetic movement and hierarchy gives the Maronites many of their distinctive features even to this day. And at some point, St. John Maron made a further choice that would contribute to the identity of the Maronites: he moved the patriarchate from Syria to Lebanon, establishing himself in a place that became known as the Holy Valley, Ouadi Qadisha. He seems to have chosen the area because the Maronite religious movement had been well established there. It's unclear exactly why the move happened, but it would prove to be important, because it made the Maronites a major feature of the mountains of Lebanon, and that turned out strategically to be a very effective place to be as first the Byzantines and then the Muslims tried to uproot the Maronites but found themselves repeatedly foiled by the difficulty of the terrain. It was a hard life, and the Maronites often had to hunker down, hide, shift their location. But it meant that they survived. They came to know the hills and forests much better than their enemies, and the natural protections of the area were formidable.

This was not obvious at the time. As far as most of the Christian world was concerned, the Maronites almost completely vanished from history, as if they had been destroyed. But then the First Crusade happened, and Raymond of Toulouse, on his way to besiege Tripoli, discovered little communities of Christians in the Lebanese hills who greeted him enthusiastically when it became clear that he, too, was Christian. The Maronites actively assisted the Crusaders and, through them, re-established active communication with Rome, whose recognition of St. John Maron as patriarch they still remembered with gratitude. And ever since, they have been the Eastern Catholic church with the closest connection to Rome.

Wednesday, February 26, 2025

And Beauty Immortal Awakes from the Tomb

 The Hermit
by James Beattie 

At the close of the day, when the hamlet is still,
And mortals the sweets of forgetfulness prove,
When nought but the torrent is heard on the hill,
And nought but the nightingale’s song in the grove:
’Twas then, by the cave of the mountain afar,
A Hermit his song of the night thus began;
No more with himself, or with nature, at war,
He thought as a sage, while he felt as a man: 

“Ah! why thus abandoned to darkness and woe?
“Why thus, lonely Philomel, flows thy sad strain?
“For spring shall return, and a lover bestow,
“And thy bosom no trace of misfortune retain.
“Yet, if pity inspire thee, ah! cease not thy lay,
“Mourn, sweetest complainer! man calls thee to mourn:
“O sooth him, whose pleasures like thine pass away--
“Full quickly they pass—but they never return. 

“Now gliding remote on the verge of the sky,
“The moon, half-extinguished, her crescent displays:
“But lately I marked, when majestic on high,
“She shone, and the planets were lost in her blaze.
“Roll on, thou fair orb, and with gladness pursue
“The path that conducts thee to splendour again:
“But man’s faded glory no change shall renew--
“Ah fool! to exult in a glory so vain! 

“Tis night, and the landscape is lovely no more:
“I mourn, but, ye woodlands, I mourn not for you;
“For morn is approaching, your charms to restore,
“Perfumed with fresh fragrance, and glittering with dew.
“Nor yet for the ravage of winter I mourn;
“Kind Nature the embryo blossom will save.--
“But when shall Spring visit the mouldering urn?
“O, when shall it dawn on the night of the grave?” 

’Twas thus, by the glare of false science betrayed,
That leads, to bewilder, and dazzles, to blind;
My thoughts wont to roam, from shade onward to shade,
Destruction before me, and sorrow behind.
“O pity, great Father of light,” then I cried,
“Thy creature, who fain would not wander from Thee!
“Lo! humbled in dust, I relinquish my pride:
“From doubt and from darkness thou only canst free.” 

And darkness and doubt are now flying away:
No longer I roam in conjecture forlorn.
So breaks on the traveller, faint, and astray,
The bright and the balmy effulgence of morn.
See Truth, Love, and Mercy, in triumph descending,
And Nature all glowing in Eden’s first bloom!
On the cold cheek of Death smiles and roses are blending,
And Beauty immortal awakes from the tomb!

Tuesday, February 25, 2025

Carr on the Four Cardinal Virtues

 It would appear, then, that the four traditional virtues of wisdom, justice, courage and temperance may be defended as cardinal in terms of the four theses stated earlier in this paper. They are cardinal in so far as they do not appear to be mutually reducible, reference to each of them is indispensable for a full account of moral virtue and they represent the four main types of virtue of which all other particular non-cardinal virtues may be considered tokens (although any particular virtue may, as Plato might have said, partake of the forms of one or more of the four main types; chastity, for example, may be some sort of mixture with respect to sexual life of wisdom, justice and temperance). Finally, there are just four cardinal virtues, no more or less, because between them they would appear to safeguard human nature in all of the areas in which moral failure or error may occur in human affairs; harmful or excessive indulgence in sensual pleasure, misconduct under the influence of emotion or passion, unjust treatment of others through self-love or pride and careless or foolish conduct following from ignorance or a defect of wisdom.

David Carr, "The Cardinal Virtues and Plato's Moral Psychology", The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 38, No. 151 (Apr., 1988), p. 200.

Sunday, February 23, 2025

Sell Not Thy Soul to Brittle Joy

 Man's Civil War
by St. Robert Southwell 

My hovering thoughts would fly to heaven
 And quiet nestle in the sky,
Fain would my ship in Virtue's shore
 Without remove at anchor lie. 

 But mounting thoughts are haled down
 With heavy poise of mortal load,
And blust'ring storms deny my ship
 In Virtue's haven secure abode. 

 When inward eye to heavenly sights
 Doth draw my longing heart's desire,
The world with jesses of delights
 Would to her perch my thoughts retire, 

 Fond Fancy trains to Pleasure's lure,
 Though Reason stiffly do repine;
Though Wisdom woo me to the saint,
 Yet Sense would win me to the shrine. 

 Where Reason loathes, there Fancy loves,
 And overrules the captive will;
Foes senses are to Virtue's lore,
 They draw the wit their wish to fill. 

 Need craves consent of soul to sense,
 Yet divers bents breed civil fray;
Hard hap where halves must disagree,
 Or truce of halves the whole betray! 

 O cruel fight! where fighting friend
 With love doth kill a favoring foe,
Where peace with sense is war with God,
 And self-delight the seed of woe! 

 Dame Pleasure's drugs are steeped in sin,
 Their sugared taste doth breed annoy;
O fickle sense! beware her gin,
 Sell not thy soul to brittle joy!

I missed the day, but St. Robert Southwell, after an extended period of torture and confinement, was martyred on February 21, 1595, hanged at Tyburn for the crime of high treason, due to his being a Jesuit priest and refusing to take the Oath of Supremacy. His poetry was immensely influential on the poetry and plays of the next generation, which was itself a titanic generation for both poetry and drama, so there are only a handful poets who have had as much of an influence on English literature as he.

Saturday, February 22, 2025

Friday, February 21, 2025

Dashed Off IV

 The scholar should enrich the experience of the reader rather than getting in the way of it.

"The whole world is the wealth of the faithful." Proverbs 17:6A (i.e., in the LXX and Vetus Latina)

mere fictions vs grounded fictions

In the way Schellenberg characterizes 'nonresistance' in the divine hiddenness argument, it is unclear if any *theists* are 'nonresistant', as opposed to merely having overcome resistance.

Terrain is half of tactics.

the tinker method (of engineering, of education, of charitable work...)

Mt 6:12 // Sir 28:2

"If a man receives the body of the Son of Man as the Bread of Life, he will have life in him." John 6:56 Vetus Latina

What we proclaim is both testimony and mystery.

By shedding error, we come to understanding; by revering truth, we come to wisdom.

The problem with the ignorance diagnosis of free will is that it requires exaggerating how ignorant we could possibly be, and (setting aside Spinoza and a few others) underestimates the kind of causes that would have to fill the gaps in order to be adequate.

People seem to forget that protesting only works if you don't come across as fringe loons.

contingent : final cause :: categorical : formal cause

unrestricted universe of discourse as logical analogue of ens ut primum cognitum

In the Church, things that are taught by infallible teaching are also taught by means that are themselves fallible.

public festivals as a mode of lay teaching

To be able to be taught by infallible means, a doctrine must be formally revealed, either in the plain letter of Scripture, or in Scritpure as understood by perpetual tradition of the Church, or it must be intimately connected with truth so revealed, either in being required for teaching it, or in being required for defending it, or in being required for living according to it.

human nature in integriity, in fall, in grace, and in glory (De Moor: instituted, destituted, restituted, constituted)

The lowest point of human degradation generally involves the attempt of the degraded to justify their degradation; this is usually more easily reached with self-imposed degradation than externally imposed degradation.

good as first willed and the limitless possibility in human action, action that can take into account the very universe itself

kinds of positive legislation
(1) customary
(2) constitutional (impositional)
(3) contractual
(4) petitionary
-- what we often think of as legislation today is a stylized version of (4) -- i.e., a bill is a stylized bill of petition, which is then deliberated over and approved or not.

Representation in government depends on the power to enforce obligations.

orders of fictional truths
(1) explicitly stated
(2) logically implied
(3) plausibly suggested
(4) scaffolding (used by author in writing; director in shooting; actor in determining motives; etc.)
(5) potentializing (what the author would /expects to assume if anything further is done)

Rage, even when understandable, is always a deterioration and often a degradation.

"All material practical principles are, without exception, of one and the same kidn and come under the general principle of self-love or one's own happiness." Kant
--> This is certainly false, for reasons noted by Butler.

Kant takes moral motivation to be self-love restricted to agreement with moral law.

correspondence with resemblance vs correspondence without resemblance

Every time Luke is mentioned in the New Testament, Mark is also mentioned.

1 Timothy 5:18 seems to call Luke 10:7 scripture
Pauls' description of the Last Supper is closest to Luke's

The Old Testament that Christians inherited was that of both Judean and Hellenistic Jews.

It takes work and cultivation of ability to seek knowledge for its own sake.

"All virtues are in our True Lord and Master; we are utterly without virtue. O Creator Lord, all are in Your Power." Sri Guru Granth Sahib 17
"The truthful are absorbed into the True Lord." 18
"The True Guru leads us to meet the Immaculate True God through the Word of His Shabad." 27
"He Himself dyes us in the Color of His Love; through the Word of His Shabad, He unites us with Himself. The True Color shall not fade away, for those who are attuned to His Love." 37
"The Word of the Gurmukh is God Himself. Throught he Shabad, we merge in Him." 39
"The True Guru, the Primal Being, is the Pool of Ambrosial Nectar. The blessed come to bathe in it." 40
"Even the ungrateful ones are cherished by God. O Nanak, He is forever the Forgiver." 47
"God Himself acts, and causes others to act; everything is in His Hands." 48
"The One Lord is the Doer, the Cause of causes, who has created the creation." 51

nadar: glance/favorable regard / favor; the glance of God's grace

"The real joy of a book lies in reading it over and over again, and always finding it different, coming upon another meaning, another level of meaning." D. H. Lawrence

For statutes to function as law, first principles of reason must already be functioning as law.

Parts of pictures of something are not necessarily pictures of parts of it (e.g., they may be symbolic abbreviations).

Our congruous merit occurs within a covenant (pactum).

predilection -> election -> predestination

Most analytic work on grounding confuses categorical relations and transcendental relations.

"Mary is holy, Mary is blessed, but the Church is something much better than the Virgin Mary. Why? Because Mary is part of the Church, a holy member, a quite exceptional member, the supremely wonderful member, but novertheless a member of the whole body." Augustine (Sermon 72a.7

miracles as tracing out aspects of divine sovereignty

Evangelium vitae 62: "direct abortion, whether intended as end or as means is always a grave moral disorder, inasmuch as it is the deliberate elimination of an innocent human being"

The Old Covenant is not shed but is fulfilled in such a way that Gentiles may participate in it through Christ.

"Signum importat aliquod notum quoad nos, quo manducimur in alterius cognitionem." Aquinas Sent 4.1.1.1q2

Perceving the world around us, we get a feeling for its invariances; having a feeling for its invariances, we reflect on them, compare and contrast them, classify them, reason about them.

Human beings cannot act without taking our bodies to be meaningul and teleological, because in humana ction we recognize this (for example) as a hand, as a means of grasping, as mine for using, as me. We are soaked in meaning and vibrant with purpose, rich in orienting and full of signifying.

The devil woos with shallow benefits.

Three elements of probable inference: possibility, appropriateness, nonimpedance. Probable inference coverge on proof as positive reasons for possibility and independent grounds of appropriateness increase, and as impediments decrease, and as the reasons in each improve in quality.

positive laws as arising from the overlaps of senses of honor, the convergence of codes of honor twoard law

Another person may be experienced as a context, an opposition, a gift, or some mix of the three.

summons, surprise, address, and fact as mode sin which the world expresses itself in inquiry

"Everything written with vitality expresses that vitality: there are no dull subjects, only dull minds." Raymond Chandler
"All language begins with speech, and the speech of common men at that, but when it develops to the point of becoming a literary medium, it only looks like speech."

"The ability to lie effectively, to appear different than one really is -- all the disguises essential in the world of power -- become, in the world of love, temptations, artful excuses to avoid the nakeness love requries, to avoid love." Josiah Thompson

'presentation' as translation of 'species' -- impressed presentation, expressed presentation, intelligible presentation, etc.

Being ut primum cognitum is being as involved in everything and thus not inquantum ens, as itself considered in itself.

A problem with social media platforms is that they train a particular kind of personality into habitual lying.

common sense as "a rough sketch of metaphysics, a vigorous and unreflective sketch" (Maritain)

Horror as a genre is about boundary violations of a certain kind; thus it must presuppose some boundaries. The usual boundaries are physical (body horror), mental (madness), and religious (transgression of sacred bound). Further, the violation must be culpable (moral horror) or piacular (tragic horror) or intrusive (alien horror). The violation may also be an incident or something that spreads (stain, contagion, or infestation). And, of course, one can combine all of these in various ways.

Being as first known jumbles together substantial being, accidental being, being in the guise of another (e.g., ficitonalized or idealized or under-an-aspect being), and being of reason.

Englert's version of Kant's Third Critique moral proof ("Kant as a Carpenter of Reason: The Highest Good and Systematic Coherence")
(1) Philosophy ought to provide a coherent account of experience as a whole. [Philosophical Demand]
(2) Judging experience as a whole leads to two necessary ideas, [a] morality and [b] nature, that ought to figure into a coherent account. [Fact of Experience & 1]
(3) A coherent account between [a] and [b] requires the highest good as a common point of reference. [Result of Ethico-Teleological Reflection & 2]
(4) The highest good can only be thought of as really possible if we postulate a further idea, namely [c] God, as "another causality." [Philosophical Postulate & 3]
(5) Therefore we must believe in God in order to do as we philosophically ought to do, namely, provide a coherent account of experience as a whole. [1 & 4]

Half of being a good author is understanding the story you are telling; this is far more difficult than it sounds, and many would-be writers fail at it, and even accomplished authors sometimes slip.

Certainties are of different kinds and are not all completely commensurable.

wrongous/wrongwise

Every theory contains realist and instrumentalist components.

"Poetry is unquestionably the language of nature; and, as such, ought to interest and impress, where it may not be able to inspire." Anna Seward

gut flora as categorically inernal vestment (habitus)

Vestment as a category concerns the fact that one substance can be as it were an accident for another substance. (It is specifically the relationality that is the vestment/cladding.)

integration of substance into substance
(1) organic part: incomplete substance into complete substance, substantially as complete part
(2) prosthetic part: incomplete substance into complete substance, substantially as incomplete part
(3) cladding/vestment: complete substance into complete substance, accidentally as actual quasi-part.
(4) separate tool: complete substance into complete substance, accidentally as a means for action and potential quasi-part

adornment : vestment as sign :: equipment : vestment as means
(manifestation and instrumentation)

Substance and relation as said transcendentally are ways of talking about one being -- being and unity both.

God as one being is imitated by creatures both substantially and relationally.

It is the civil society, not the state, that is the embodiment of all political right.

the juridical commonwealth as a symbol fo the ethical commonwealth

Kant's arguments that Judaism is a politics rather than a religion
(1) Its commands relate only to external acts. --> This is clearly not the law as interpreted by the prophets.
(2) It limits reward and punishment to this world. --> This requires to taking teh world to come as part of 'this world', and also ignores remembrance before the Lord.
(3) The concept of a chosen people shows enmity to other people. --> On the contrary, inherently the opposite: Jews as the universally mediating nation, the priestly people among all just peoples.

Albert on the eucharist
(1) body: communion
(2) blood: atonement
**
(3) soul: redemption
(4) spirit: vivification & virtue
**
(5) divinity: refreshment
**
--> as a whole: beatitude

The Eucharist has signs of both Body and Blood because the Body is the best as a symbol of fellowship and communion and the Blood as a symbol of sacrifice and atonement, both of which are essential aspects of this sacrament.

Everything becomes more stupid in committee, and Jesus never promises that committees of bishops are exceptions.

Augustine, Confessions Bk X.8.15 -- the sublimity of memory

"If we remember even the fact that we have forgotten, we have not entirely forgotten." Augustine
"The happy life, in fact, is joy in truth: and that means joy in You, who are Truth, O God my light, the health of my consequence, my God."

We form the image of the future and are formed in the image of the past.

Protestant treatment of the plain text of Scripture has an odd tendency to oscillate between reading Scripture as if one were brain-damaged (very literal, ignoring suggestive juxtapositions, bypassing the sorts of symbolisms readers generally find in even elementary human texts) and reading it as if it were a technical object of academic analysis, requiring elaborate apparatus and sophistication and expertise to read. In fact the plain text touches each of these poles and covers all in between.

Medium et Principium demonstationis est quod quid est.

We do not use 'what is' to demonstrate; instead use 'what the *what* is' (quiddity) to demonstrate.

"The object of the mind is what the what is, that is, the very being of something.... And thus a likeness of something in the mind is directly a likneess of its being, whereas a likeness of something in snesation or imagination is a likeness of its incidentals." Aquinas