Monday, May 05, 2014

Elements of Modal Logic I

When dealing with arguments we generally have a universe of discourse; 'universe of discourse' in the sense used here is the category that includes all the things that are relevant to the argument and leaves out all the things that are not relevant to it. It is presupposed by everything in the argument. For instance, if I say, "Dragons breathe fire," it matters considerably whether we are talking about characters in a story or real-life monitor lizards.

Imagine we had a table corresponding to this universe of discourse; on this table we could write whatever premises might be used. So, for instance, we might have a very simple table, corresponding to a particular group of men, on which we've written:

TABLE 1
Socrates is strange.
Plato is not strange, but elegant.
Aristotle is not strange, but bossy.


We could then put these together in ways logically implied by these premises, and say that these things are true at Table 1.

But we don't always assume the same category. For instance, Table 1 might correspond to a particular group of men at a certain time. We might then also be interested in the same particular group of men at a different time. So we could have different tables. If Table 1 is the group of men on Tuesday, perhaps another thing we are interested in is the same group of men on Wednesday, so we can make another table corresponding to that, e.g.:

TABLE 2
Socrates is strange.
Plato is strange.
Aristotle is not strange, but bossy.


Strictly speaking, each table has its own logical operations and conclusions. For instance, on Table 1, we can conclude that neither Plato nor Aristotle are strange; but on Table 2, this is false. This is not a contradiction, since in drawing each of these conclusions we only stay on the relevant table, and don't leap from one to the other.

But we may also be interested in how they related to each other. And we certainly can say something about that. For instance, we can say, if these are our only two tables, "If we're looking at these tables, we would always find that Socrates is strange." We can also say, "We can find a table on which Plato is strange." In our example, the tables in question are interpreted as days, but they could be anything else. We could have tables that represent cities, possible worlds, stories, or whatever we please.

At its most crude and basic, this is all that modal logic is. "On any table, we would find that Socrates is strange" is a Box proposition; it is said to have a strong modality. "We can find a table on which Plato is strange" is a Diamond proposition; it is said to have a weak modality.

Even this on its own is, logically speaking, very important. But there is much more that could be done. For instance, we've been assuming that it's perfectly straightforward what you have to do to find a table on which a claim is found. But it could be that there are restrictions on how we find tables; and, as it happens, depending on how we interpret the table, we often want there to be different kinds of restrictions on which tables we can talk about under which circumstances. There might be tables that we can find if we start at one table but not if we start at another. Likewise, it's possible that one of the claims we have on a table tells us something about other tables, or about what we will find if we find any other tables. And in practice, most of what is dealt with in modal logic has not to do with general statements about tables as a whole, but about how they relate to each other given different assumptions and interpretations. I hope to begin discussing this a bit in a future post.

This is the first post in a series in which I'm experimenting with finding the simplest possible ways to teach the basics of modal logic at an undergraduate level, so that, for instance, one could introduce serious and substantive discussions of modal arguments into an intro-level class, or, for that matter, a high-school class, without taxing the students with too many technicalities more suitable to a higher-level course. The word 'experiment' is used advisedly.

7 comments:

  1. Sleep well knowing I will butcher this into working for my "60 Seconds of Logic" daily warm-up with high school freshmen.

    ReplyDelete
  2. branemrys7:53 PM

    My pedagogical evilness is spreading!

    You'll have to let me know how it goes. But it should be workable, as long as they've already had some experience with how arguments work -- that's basically working on one table, and modal logic just generalizes so that we can work on several at a time.

    ReplyDelete
  3. MrsDarwin7:38 AM

    I like this. Keep working on it, and have it all ready for me in two years, when my oldest hits ninth grade.

    ReplyDelete
  4. I don't know if I can make it work in my time constraints, but it will be fun to try. If I run my warm-ups every day, I can get them to know basics about terms, propositions, conversion, the square, figures, etc. in the fall semester...modal might be reachable by end of spring, or at least as an optional module for students who have the knack.

    ReplyDelete
  5. branemrys8:03 AM

    Will do!

    ReplyDelete
  6. branemrys8:06 AM

    In principle it can be handled just like quantity for propositions -- universal and particular are (I would argue) just a particular case of Box and Diamond, which is why we can get conversion, the square, etc. for modalities like necessity (Box) and possibility (Diamond), too. (It's also why I've started with singular subjects in my examples.)

    ReplyDelete
  7. I had just picked up Aristotle's "On Sophistical Refutations" when I read this post! Even if one was taught logic, I think it is beneficial to revise it periodically. For what it's worth, I would very much enjoy it if you were to continue to share your notes here, though it is no easy task to teach the basics clearly and simply. "Rah rah!"

    ReplyDelete

Please understand that this weblog runs on a third-party comment system, not on Blogger's comment system. If you have come by way of a mobile device and can see this message, you may have landed on the Blogger comment page, or the third party commenting system has not yet completely loaded; your comments will only be shown on this page and not on the page most people will see, and it is much more likely that your comment will be missed.